The conflict between absolutist and anti-absolutist
political theory dominated English government during the first half of the
seventeenth century. Absolutists,
including King James I and his son Charles I, argued that sovereignty lay
solely with the monarch from who all political and religious authority flowed
due to his mandate from God.
Anti-absolutists denied the King’s absolute supremacy, arguing that the
law bound the monarch no less than it bound his subjects. The dispute between absolutists and
anti-absolutists included the proper role of Parliament, taxation,
imprisonment, and religion. The
fundamental dispute between absolutists and anti-absolutists devolves into an
issue of property rights. The absolutist
interpretation of the monarch’s power and authority is that all property is
rightfully the King’s, and that he may dispose of it at will. Anti-absolutists were concerned with the
preservation of their private property rights in the form taxes, import duties,
forced loans, benefices, and their own bodies.
Absolutists based their argument on the theory of Divine
Right of Kings. Kings received their
authority directly from God whether they became monarch through election or
conquest. The divine origin of the
King’s authority meant that his power was boundless. No laws could restrain him, and only God
could judge the King’s actions or policies.
Further, the King’s mandate from God meant that it was sedition or even
blasphemy to challenge the King’s decrees. Absolutists argued the King granted
his subjects as privileges their traditional rights of taxation only with
consent of Parliament and imprisonment only through due process. Anti-absolutists agreed that the monarch
received his authority from God, but denied that this set him above the law, or
that Parliament could not discuss or challenge his actions or policies. The monarch did not grant immunity from
imprisonment without cause or taxation without consent of Parliament as a
privilege - those rights were established under England’s ancient Anglo-Saxon
constitution.
Politics, particularly the issues of taxation and
imprisonment, were the primary arena of conflict between the two
ideologies. Taxation became an issue for
anti-absolutists when James I created new import duties without consulting
Parliament. Anti-absolutists argued that
the import duties were a new tax, and that only Parliament, consisting of the
House of Commons, House of Lords, and the King, could impose new taxes. The absolutists, led by the King argued that
the monarch had the right to act in the interests of state when Parliament was
not in session. Anti-absolutists
responded that this tradition was intended only to be used in case of emergency
to defend England from invasion, and that the King should call Parliament to
request new taxes for all other purposes.
King James’ response to the challenge from anti-absolutists was to
declare that the King could pass taxes on his own, as they were his right as monarch.
Parliament’s proper role in taxation took new meaning after
Charles I collected a forced loan from wealthy landowners in 1626, and the King
ordered five members of the gentry who refused to pay the loan as an illegal
tax imprisoned. When the knights’
lawyers requested writs of habeas corpus from the King’s Bench, the King
refused to show cause for their imprisonment because he did not want the
legality of the Forced Loan debated in court.
When the judges of the King’s Bench ruled only to withhold bail for the
knights, the King sent a courtier to attempt the court documents so they showed
that the judges ruled that the King could imprison individuals without cause.
The anti-absolutists in the House of Commons viewed these
events as an attack on yet another of their ancient rights. Charles I and his supporters fed the Commons’
fear by arguing that the King could imprison people without cause, impose
taxes, and pass legislation without Parliament due to the divine origins of his
power. Further, taxes were his rightful
due as monarch, and it was sedition to challenge his dictates or discuss his
rightful prerogatives. The proper role
of Parliament was to discuss and vote on only those things that the King told it
to discuss.
Conflict between absolutists and anti-absolutists was not
restricted to the political arena, but also included the role of the church
hierarchy. Absolutists argued that as
God’s representative on earth, the King occupied the top of the religious
hierarchy, subordinate only to God. This
position allowed the monarch to dictate what ministers preached. Absolutists believed that members of the
hierarchy could wield temporal power to imprison or fine ministers or other
individuals in ecclesiastical courts, and that it was legitimate for the
hierarchy to remove benefices given to ministers that did not preach according
to the canons.
Anti-absolutists took the opposite tack, arguing that the
Church was independent of the King, and that it could excommunicate him if he
merited it through impiety or action.
Further, the Church only possessed spiritual authority, not temporal
authority. Since they were not based in
statute, the fines and imprisonments of the ecclesiastical courts were not
legal, and the hierarchy did not have the authority to strip ministers of
benefices bestowed upon them. In effect,
anti-absolutists believed that inheritances, tithes, and benefices were
property, and subject to the common law.
There are two historiographical issues to contend with in
when considering the conflict between absolutists and anti-absolutists in
seventeenth century England: whether the conflict was primarily religious, and
whether political conflict in England suddenly manifested shortly before
1642. Johann P. Sommerville argues that
Congregationalists were such a small minority during the first half of the
seventeenth century that the disagreement over the role of the Episcopal
hierarchy was not the primary cause of the English Civil War. The role of the King in the religious
hierarchy remained a significant issue, as did the issue of the Pope’s power to
depose monarchs, but neither was the driving issue toward open conflict.
Conrad Russell offers an alternate interpretation of the
political struggles from 1600–1642 is that England’s laity was politically
united, with absolutists restricted to the clergy. Parliament widely accepted the theory that
the people could depose a tyrant, which revisionists define as an absolute
monarch who ruled poorly. Sommerville dismisses the revisionist argument by
attacking the restrictive definition of “absolutist” required to argue for
political unity. The revisionists define
absolutists only as those who believe that the King can rule by fiat, and pass
laws without resorting to Parliament. In
the revisionist interpretation, accepting the Divine Right of Kings to rule is
not enough to define an argument as absolutist.
This narrow definition of “absolutist” excludes both Bodin and Bossuet,
an apologist for Louis XIV of France, rendering it ineffective for describing
the political challenges of the era.
No comments:
Post a Comment